This is my analysis of the ICJ ruling on the legality of nuclear weapons. Elsewhere on this site is the background of the legal developments, from 1945 onward, which led to that ruling.

Gaillard T. Hunt
10705 Tenbrook Drive
Silver Spring, Maryland 20901
301-530-2807
gthunt@mdo.net

Return to home page.

 

THE WORLD COURT AND THE BOMB

 

 

Nuremberg and Babel at the Hague

 

On July 8, 1996, the World Court, the International Court of Justice at the Hague, banned the bomb. 1

This was in answer to a question certified by the UN General Assembly, "Is the threat or use of nuclear weapons in any circumstance permitted under international law?" 2 The answer was No, nuclear warfare is not permitted. The World Court has jurisdiction 3 to give such answers, and even though the Court has no more battalions than the Pope or the Archbishop of Canterbury, still it is the closest thing we have to a final authority in international law, and it is astonishing how little reaction and comment this ruling has generated. 4

In 1998, about two years after the ruling, India and Pakistan blasted their way into the nuclear club. A massive diplomatic response is now trying to persuade them to leave peacefully. 5 But the United States and the Russian Federation each have many times the deliverable warheads of all the other nuclear powers combined, 6 and present plans will allow those two arsenals to continue at omnicidal and ecocidal levels into the indefinite future. India and Pakistan can defend themselves as small contributors to the nuclear threat, negligible when compared to the United States and Russia.

Long before the Indian and Pakistani bombs, the two great nuclear arsenals were being questioned by recovering Cold Warriors with impeccable military credentials -- retired CIA chief Admiral Stansfield Turner, 7 for instance, and retired SAC commander General George Lee Butler. 8 Their old colleagues from the deep bunkers of the Iron Mountain era were finding it necessary to circle wagons and defend MAD, overkill, and the rest of the nuclear status quo. 9 The World Court's ruling shows that law has a role to play in this debate. Some of the discipline necessary to call the world back from its long flirtation with extinction may come from legal reasoning, and may even come from one of the law's most disparaged departments, international law.

Let us therefore examine the World Court's ruling. The lack of reaction and comment about the ruling may be largely the Court's own fault. The ruling consists of a formal Dispositif, 10 which seems to say there may be exceptions to the bomb's illegality; a rambling and diffuse "Advisory Opinion" by the whole Court, 11 which offers little usable analysis of the issues; and fourteen separate opinions, one from each judge, no two concurring one with another. 12 Most of the discussion is hopelessly abstract. As a political rallying point the ruling is unpromising. Clashing viewpoints and differing legal traditions from around the world, which could make the World Court an intellectual clearinghouse for the best hopes of humankind, came together, and a decision was reached to condemn the bomb. But the aspirations of Nuremberg were drowned by the confusions of Babel.

 

The Court Holds Nuclear Weapons Subject to Law

 

Let us start with the World Court's formal Dispositif. (Those with limited toleration for the splitting of hairs and the discovery of fine points in confused prose may want to skip to "The Law as It now Stands.") The Dispositif has two sections. In section (1) the Court, by a vote of thirteen to one, accepted jurisdiction and agreed to issue an advisory opinion. In (2) the Court held:

[(2)]A. Unanimously, There is in neither customary nor conventional international law any specific authorization of the threat or use of nuclear weapons;

[(2)]B. By eleven votes to three, There is in neither customary nor conventional international law any comprehensive and universal prohibition of the threat or use of nuclear weapons as such;

[(2)]C. Unanimously, A threat or use of force by means of nuclear weapons that is contrary to Article 2, paragraph 4, of the United Nations Charter and that fails to meet all the requirements of Article 51, is unlawful;

[(2)]D. Unanimously, A threat or use of nuclear weapons should also be compatible with the requirements of the international law applicable in armed conflict, particularly those of the principles and rules of international humanitarian law, as well as with specific obligations under treaties and other undertakings which expressly deal with nuclear weapons;

[(2)]E. By seven votes to seven, by the President's casting vote, It follows from the above-mentioned requirements that the threat or use of nuclear weapons would generally be contrary to the rules of international law applicable in armed conflict, and in particular the principles and rules of humanitarian law;

However, in view of the current state of international law, and of the elements of fact at its disposal, the Court cannot conclude definitively whether the threat or use of nuclear weapons would be lawful or unlawful in an extreme circumstance of self-defence, in which the very survival of a State would be at stake.

[(2)]F. Unanimously, There exists an obligation to pursue in good faith and bring to a conclusion negotiations leading to nuclear disarmament in all its aspects under strict and effective international control.

Nuclear Weapons, 35 I.L.M. 809, 831-832.

Paragraph (2)A. says there is no specific authorization for nuclear weapons. This states the obvious, but it is far from trivial. If the nuclear powers' reservations of their rights had been as successful as they claim, surely there would be some specific authorization somewhere. And this paragraph makes clear that Hiroshima and Nagasaki are not precedents amounting to such a specific authorization.

Paragraph (2)B. says there is no "comprehensive and universal prohibition of the threat or use of nuclear weapons as such." Language so loaded with qualifications cries out for explanation. It is heavy with what logicians call negatives pregnant. Two of the three judges who voted against this paragraph -- the three were Christopher G. Weeramantry of Sri Lanka, Mohamed Shahabuddeen of Guyana, and Abdul G. Koroma of Sierra Leone -- cited the 1925 Geneva Gas Protocol as such a prohibition. 13 The Court did not go along with this, so we must accept that the bold proposition that the bomb is illegal as a poisonous gas did not survive the Court's strict constructionism. One of the three judges, however, pointed to the negatives pregnant and claimed that the Court did not really deny the possibility of some nuclear prohibition: "The specificity conveyed by the words 'as such' enables me to recognize that '[t]here is in neither customary nor conventional international law any comprehensive and universal prohibition of the threat or use of nuclear weapons as such.'" 14 Nevertheless he voted against the paragraph, he said, because "the words 'as such' do not outweigh a general suggestion that there is no prohibition at all of the use of nuclear weapons." 15 Both the nuclearists and the anti-nuclearists on the Court indulged in much of this kind of hair-splitting.

In any event, it was a "comprehensive and universal" -- strong words -- "as such" prohibition that paragraph (2)B. rejected eleven to three. This rejection is trivial and meaningless as applied to customary law, which is not written down and therefore cannot prohibit anything "as such" (that is, by name, explicitly), and it is only a statement of regrettable but undeniable fact as applied to treaty law as it now stands, because the all-important Nuclear Non-Proliferation Treaty prohibits possession, not use, or it prohibits use only by implication. There is less to paragraph (2)B. than meets the eye.

The unanimous holdings of the next two paragraphs, (2)C. and (2)D., give back in practice more than paragraph (2)B. took away in theory. In these next paragraphs the Court finds nuclear weapons firmly under the moderating hand of international law. The opinion of the Court notes the general acceptance by the nuclear states that any use of nuclear weapons is "indeed restricted by the principles and rules of international law, more particularly humanitarian law. . . ." Paragraph 22. of the opinion, citing paragraph 86. 16 "A weapon that is already unlawful per se, whether by treaty or custom, does not become lawful by reason of its being used for a legitimate purpose under the Charter [i.e., self-defense]," and even self-defense is subject to the rules of necessity and proportionality. Paragraphs 41.-44. Any use of nuclear weapons must take account not only of the effects of the immediate use but also of the retaliatory use it is likely to engender. Paragraph 43. So any conceivable use of nuclear weapons would be illegal. All the negatives pregnant in paragraph (2)B. are indeed gravid with significance, and there are customary prohibitions against nuclear weapons, even if they are not, to the Continental legalist, entirely "comprehensive" and "universal" and against nuclear weapons "as such."

 

The Court Condemns Nuclear Weapons "Generally"

 

If the Dispositif stopped there, anti-nuclearism would be far ahead. But there is the exasperating puzzle of paragraph (2)E.

A majority of the Court felt there must be some limit on their condemnation of nuclear weapons, or at least on their expression of it. Paragraph 95. of the Opinion says:

. . . In view of the unique characteristics of nuclear weapons, to which the Court has referred above, the use of such weapons in fact seems scarcely reconcilable with respect for such requirements [the principles and rules of law applicable in armed conflict]. Nevertheless, the Court considers that it does not have sufficient elements to enable it to conclude with certainty that the use of nuclear weapons would necessarily be at variance with the principles and rules of law applicable in armed conflict in any circumstance.

Nuclear Weapons, 35 I.L.M. 809, 829.

Most jurists, moralists, and logicians would accept this as a hand-wringing confession of the inevitable limits of human wisdom and language. But when the same thought appears in paragraph (2)E. of the Dispositif, it has become linked to "an extreme circumstance of self-defence, in which the very survival of a State would be at stake." Would this mean that the Japanese could have legally used the bomb against America, had they had it in 1945? 17 Or that Hitler could have put nuclear warheads in his V-2s? 18 An apparently alarming concession, but the Court does not say nuclear weapons would be legal in such cases. The Court refuses to rule one way or the other.

The Court has been keeping the discussion on the level of abstract rules and principles, and avoiding concrete situations, real or hypothetical. Some of the judges seem to have in mind an all-out nuclear exchange, while others may be speculating about limited battlefield uses of tactical warheads under special and well-controlled circumstances, while still others struggle for a formula that would cover all conceivable scenarios with the phrase "nuclear weapons" in them. This may be inevitable in an advisory opinion, which does not give a court the pragmatic benefit of a factual situation. But here at the eleventh hour one hypothetical -- and a hypothetical hypothetical at that -- is sneaked in and given prominent place. We could use more discussion of hypotheticals, or we could do without this one.

The individual opinions put all this in a better light. Four 19 of the seven 20 judges who voted against this paragraph, (2)E., said explicitly that they objected only to the limits on the condemnation of nuclear weapons, and that they thought the condemnation should have been absolute. Only one of the dissenting seven, Judge Schwebel, candidly argued for the legality of the bomb. 21 (This leaves two who were ambiguous or unclear, Guillaume 22 and Higgins. 23 ) Of the seven 24 who voted for the paragraph not one of them expressly said he would have voted against it had it been stronger and had the condemnation been without limits. 25 No matter how the limitations got in there, there remain both a clear statement that most use of the bomb would be illegal, and a clear majority of judges believing all use would be illegal.

 

The Non-Proliferation Treaty Bans Possession

 

Whatever the cautionary negatives in the first several paragraphs of the Dispositif, the tone changes in the final paragraph, (2)F. There the Court lays down the law and spells out a clear and unequivocal obligation for future action: the nuclear signatories of the Non-Proliferation Treaty must give up their nuclear weapons. In the background section we discussed how that treaty became a bargain between the nuclear states and the non-nuclear states, with the nuclear states agreeing to Article VI:

Each of the Parties to the Treaty undertakes to pursue negotiations in good faith on effective measures relating to cessation of the nuclear arms race at an early date and to nuclear disarmament, and on a treaty on general and complete disarmament under strict and effective international control.

Nuclear Non-Proliferation Treaty, Article VI, quoted in Nuclear Weapons, 35 I.L.M. 809, 830.

 

The last paragraph of the Dispositif holds the signatory nuclear states to this agreement. It unanimously decrees that these nuclear powers are obliged to negotiate complete nuclear disarmament. Paragraph 99. of the opinion of the Court amplifies this:

. . . The legal import of that obligation goes beyond that of a mere obligation of conduct; the obligation involved here is an obligation to achieve a precise result -- nuclear disarmament in all its aspects -- by adopting a particular course of conduct, namely, the pursuit of negotiations on the matter in good faith.

Nuclear Weapons, 35 I.L.M. 809, 830.

The Court went on to support this voluntarily incurred treaty obligation, this promise made by each nuclear power to all the other states signing the Non-Proliferation Treaty, by citing General Assembly resolutions from the very first 26 onward, 27 and the statements of the 1995 NPT review conference. 28 Thus the Court squarely rejected the notion that the post-Cold War world order might include the United States and the Russian Federation bristling with thousands of nuclear weapons each.

 

Nations Outside the Non-Proliferation Treaty

 

When the Court discusses possession, it takes the course of least resistance and most certainty by leaving unwritten law behind and focusing on the Non-Proliferation Treaty. Little did anyone know how dramatically attention would shift two years later to nations outside the Treaty, when two of them, India and Pakistan, would write in subterranean fire the questions the Court neglected to answer: Is it lawful under international law, outside of the Non-Proliferation Treaty, for a nation to arm itself with a nuclear weapon? Is it lawful even if the nation in question has a traditional enemy which is sure to respond by similarly arming itself? Is it lawful to start or join a nuclear arms race?

The arguments against the lawfulness of any nation, even one outside the Treaty, acquiring a nuclear weapon are many. Acquiring a nuclear weapon, especially where one's adversaries are likely to acquire it too, is a threat to international peace and security. So the UN Security Council decreed in 1992: "The proliferation of all weapons of mass destruction constitutes a threat to international peace and security. . . .". 29 If use of nuclear weapons is a crime against humanity, then preparation for use must be at least an inchoate illegality. And when a treaty commands as much acceptance as has the Non-Proliferation Treaty, 30 it may be declaratory of the jus cogens, the general principles binding on all. 31 Perhaps nations gain nothing by holding back their signature. We can assume that all these arguments are being made to Indian and Pakistan -- and to Israel as well, one hopes. But the World Court did not explicitly address the question of nations outside the Nuclear Non-Poliferation Treaty.

 

The Judges' Separate Opinions

The fourteen separate opinions, one from every member of the Court, suggest by their very bulk that the dispositif and its limitations may not be the optimum set of compromises. It is too much to expect that fourteen judges using different languages and grounded in differing legal traditions might sharpen issues as effectively as, for instance, the nine members of the U.S. Supreme Court often do. But we cannot help but wish that their output might have been both shorter and clearer.

 

The Anti-Nuclearists

 

Three of the separate opinions, long as they are, make good reading for the anti-nuclearist: Christopher G. Weeramantry of Sri Lanka covered 88 pages (about 50,000 words) with arguments against the bomb; 32 Mohamed Shahabuddeen of Guyana 35 pages (about 20,000 words); 33 and Abdul G. Koroma of Sierra Leone, 19 pages (about 10,000 words). 34

Koroma was one of the judges mentioned above who voted against paragraph (2)C. because they believed that the gas protocols and other conventions do ban nuclear weapons "as such," and he voted against paragraph (2)E. because he read the Nuremberg tribunal as saying a state's right to insure its own survival is not unlimited, 35 and the ICJ's own Nicaragua case 36 likewise. He found the fifty-year tradition of non-use amply backed by an opinio juris against the bomb, making it binding law. 37 In one of the few references 38 to Hiroshima and Nagasaki by any member of the Court, Koroma said:

. . . It should not be forgotten that the Second World War had witnessed the use of the atomic weapon in Hiroshima and Nagasaki, resulting in the deaths of thousands of human beings. The Second World War therefore came to be regarded as the period epitomizing gross violations of human rights. . . .

Nuclear Weapons, Opinion of Koroma, 35 I.L.M. 809, 925, 928-929.

Koroma dismissed the distinction between treaty law, admittedly binding, and humanitarian customary law, which the United States and others had urged the Court to leave to political consideration. 39 He cited several authorities rejecting such a double standard and holding that the humanitarian side of customary law is part of the jus cogens binding on all. 40

Weeramantry and Shahabuddeen were as anti-nuclear as Koroma, and wrote at greater length. The idea that nuclear weapons are essentially a gas and are prohibited by the anti-gas protocols 41 was rejected by the majority of the Court, but other points remain arguable law.

 

The Candid Nuclearist

 

The only unabashed apologist for the bomb was the American, Judge Harold Schwebel, Vice President of the Court. Schwebel served for many years in the office of the Legal Advisor in the U.S. State Department. His opinion begins:

More than any case in the history of the Court, this proceeding presents a titanic tension between State practice and legal principle.

Nuclear Weapons, Opinion of Schwebel, 35 I.L.M. 809, 836.

He claims that for a half-century the threat to use nuclear weapons has been clear and constant from the major states, states that represent "the bulk of the world's military and economic and financial and technological power and a very large proportion of its population." 42 But we know that the vast majority of states do not possess nuclear weapons, and those that possess them seldom or never make threats, even implicitly, and have not used a nuclear weapon since 1945. This more accurate view of state practice would take some of the Titanic out of Judge Schwebel's tension between practice and principle.

Schwebel takes similar liberties by enlisting the treaty regimes of the last half century on the pro-nuclear side of his tension: all the limited nuclear bans, such as the Non-Proliferation Treaty, legitimize that which they do not ban, he argues. 43 He carries this to the extreme of reading the assurances of non-use the nuclear powers gave to the non-aligned, non-nuclear signatories of the Non-Proliferation Treaty as implying the threat to use nuclear weapons elsewhere. 44 As for the anti-nuclear General Assembly resolutions, Schwebel requires that such resolutions be "adopted unanimously (or virtually so, qualitatively as well as quantitatively) or by consensus . . ." before they become evidence of the world's opinio juris. 45 Thus he claims that the resolutions passed by mere majorities serve only to show the law is the opposite of what they say.

Schwebel accepts 46 the concessions of the nuclear powers that any nuclear use is subject to the humanitarian principles of law. Those principles are what make up the anti-nuclear side of his tension. He agrees that there is a problem in the deterrence theory of the nuclear states: it rests on a professed willingness to incinerate millions of civilians with no conceivable proportionality to any legitimate military objective, and such behavior is against generally accepted principles of humanitarian law. Faced with this contradiction, Schwebel comes close to concurring with the Court's anti-nuclear ruling:

The use of nuclear weapons is, for the reasons examined above, exceptionally difficult to reconcile with the rules of international law applicable in armed conflict, particularly the principles and rules of international humanitarian law.

Nuclear Weapons, Opinion of Schwebel, 35 I.L.M. 809, 836, 840.

Further to his credit, Schwebel puts forth some hypotheticals. What if a rogue submarine were destroying cities and killing and threatening to kill millions? Ordinary depth charges are powerless against it. Would it be illegal to hit it with a nuclear depth charge, a clean nuclear explosion that would save the threatened cities with no collateral damage, fallout, or risk of escalation?

We asked for hypotheticals, so it is only fair that we give our enthusiastic endorsement to this virtuous nuclear explosion. It sounds as wholesome as a nuclear bomb vaporizing a giant meteor headed toward the earth, 47 and about as likely. In the post-nuclear world, there will be no submarines capable of killing millions, and the greater safety lies in seeing that such incapacity comes about as soon as possible. 48 A legal rule should condemn a source of danger, not condone it in the hope that it might possibly in some extraordinary case serve as a homeopathic antidote to itself. Schwebel's interest in this hypothetical reflects the same view as the United States' filing with the Court, 49 the view that the Court should not attempt to synthesize a verbal rule unless a treaty has led the way and supplied the rule, and that any rule as verbalized must be indefeasible by any conceivable set of circumstances. There is some authority for this kind of judicial restraint in the healthy maxim nullum poenum sine legem -- no punishment without a law -- but as far as major crimes against humanity are concerned, it was conclusively rejected at Nuremberg.

The underlying problem with Schwebel's approach is his allocation of burdens of legal persuasion. If he encounters a divided view on any nuclear issue, it is nuclearism that prevails, and suggested restraint that must bear the risk of non-persuasion. He rests this on the adage that that which is not prohibited is allowed -- a sound principle, but one which does not apply to mass destruction. With mass destruction, that which is not specifically and affirmatively justified, and brought within some extraordinary license, is illicit -- because mass destruction is generally illicit. Schwebel's approach is well illustrated by some speculations about the 1991 Gulf War that take up the final pages of his opinion. Tariq Aziz, the Iraqi Foreign Minister, has claimed that Iraq had been ready to use chemical and biological warfare but was deterred by the veiled nuclear threats of U.S. Secretary of State Baker. 50 Schwebel offers this as an instance of the bomb having a healthy effect. His logic here is the eternal logic of bellicism: the bomb gets credit for everything the Iraqis did not do, however speculative their ability to do it, but need accept no embarrassment for what they actually did do in defiance of the same deterrent.

But putting aside this fundamentally misplaced presumption of regularity, Schwebel's opinion presents issues at the crux of this case:

1. How are the opinions of nations to be weighed? Do the great powers outweigh the rest of the world, in determining legal consensus? Or are all foreign offices created equal? Or does the truth lie between these two extremes?

2. To what extent should any office or any commentator, such as the International Court of Justice, limit its discussion of international law to written treaties, and dismiss the opinion of humanity because it is diffuse and ill-defined?

3. Do the unwritten principles of humanitarian law ever ban a particular weapon, or must those principles always address only the results accomplished, whatever the weapon?

The first question will disappear if and when the United States and the other nuclear powers cease opposing the rest of the world on the legality of nuclear arms. The Court's ruling answers the second question for the International Court of Justice at the Hague: The unwritten law of humanitarian restraint is as real there as it was at Nuremberg a half-century ago. 51 The third question remains as the last-ditch defense of nuclearism: maybe we can't use our nuclear weapons and maybe we are obliged to get rid of them, but just don't say that they are illegal per se. The nuclearists' world may end not with a bang but a quibble.

We can be grateful to Schwebel for his clarity and candor. He voted against paragraph (2) E. because he saw no illegality in the use of nuclear weapons, and a clear majority of the Court voted that theory down.

 

The Law as it Now Stands

 

Our review of the World Court's work has perhaps smacked of ingratitude. The International Court of Justice is the closest we have to a final authority in international law (even if it is not one, because nations reserve the right to ignore its opinions) and when such an authority condemns the bomb, it seems ungrateful to complain of obscurity or lack of clarity. The World Court accomplished much. Because of its efforts we can now declare large areas of law settled. Let us try to outline the law as it now stands.

First, some obvious distinctions:

-- Categories of nuclear acts: research, development, acquisition, stockpiling, deployment, threatening to use, and actual use of nuclear weapons.

-- Categories of use: peaceful explosions, testing, and the possible combat uses, all of which have been hypothetical since 1945: tactical use in controllable situations, limited escalations, counterforce escalations, countervalue escalations, urbicide, genocide, omnicide, ecocide, etc.

-- Sources of law: customs joined with an opinio juris, including the basic humanitarian laws of war; treaty regimes, also confusingly called conventional law; and fully implemented rules acknowledged by states and conveyed to their officials by laws, orders, and regulations; etc.

-- Criteria of legality: rules that forbid a given instrument per se, and rules that forbid certain instruments because of the unlikelihood that they can be used legally; rules that forbid a weapon by name, and those that denounce it by description; etc.

With all of this factual and conceptional variety, and the general lack of institutional settlement in international law, there is much we cannot say with authority. But if we focus on the use of nuclear weapons, we find these points are now generally accepted by nuclear and non-nuclear states alike:

1. Any military use of nuclear weapons is subject to the unwritten principles of humanitarian law, the law referred to in the Martens clause. 52

2. These principles ban the targeting of civilians. 53

3. They also require economy and proportionality even when the targets are military. 54

While the nuclear powers accept these points, they seem to have trouble with what obviously follows: that any nuclear exchange would be against international law 55 -- as well as violating every other standard of human conduct. So would any nuclear bombing of any city. 56 Only the most unlikely hypothetical use -- against Schwebel's rogue submarine, for instance -- could avoid collateral consequences of escalation and fallout enough to escape a ringing condemnation by "the requirements of the public conscience." Even the smallest of "tactical" nuclear artillery would bring down on the nation or group using it the odium of humankind for crossing the nuclear threshold. 57

Thus the half-century of non-use is not a legal irrelevancy. It has given rise to law as clear as any written on paper and signed at conference tables, and breaking it would cost any nation or group dearly. Counsellors who try to define this law out of existence will regret their words should anyone ever be foolish enough to act upon their advice.

 

 

 

 

Whither Now?

 

Apart from all the considerations discussed above, humanitarian law as well as treaty law should have something to say about the sheer mass of the two largest nuclear arsenals, even after their post-Cold War reductions, because no conceivable military or political threat could justify the risks of omnicide and ecocide involved. There are several distinct principles at work here: Any acquisition of a nuclear bomb is destabilizing and a threat, and should be denounced as illegally aggressive under the Charter, 58 in addition to its illegality under the Non-Proliferation Treaty. But quite separate from this, and antecedent to even the simplest attempts at forming international law, when a nuclear arsenal reaches the size that it becomes a threat to the life of the planet itself as well as a threat to the peace, it must acquire yet another type of illegality. None of this is covered in the Court's opinion.

The Russian Federation and NATO have switched places since the days of John Foster Dulles, but still the weaker side sees its nuclear weapons as an cheap substitute for the prohibitively expensive buildup it would need to reach a balance of conventional forces. This was American doctrine under Truman and Eisenhower, 59 when faced with the massive Red Army sprawled over half of Europe, and it is the doctrine of the Russians now, faced with NATO expanding into former Soviet satellites. It would dramatically enhance the American margin of power if the nuclear weapons were out of the order of battle.

On most of the above legal questions, the United States professes doctrines different from the rest of the world. That is the chief source of legal obscurity. Judge Schwebel and others find benefit in this obscurity. This is the crux of this matter: Which is safer, a world professing the illegality of nuclear weapons, and seeking to suppress them by that illegality, or a world professing their legitimacy, and hoping to hold them in check by their own dangerous effects, such as nuclear diplomacy and nuclear terror? Since the issue is not capable of experimental resolution, the answer must turn on presumptions and judgment. When it comes to the omnicidal arsenals now in place, and to the proposed retention of enough of those arsenals for multiple genocides, the world must vote down Judge Schwebel, his former colleagues in the Department of State, and those of like mind in the Russian Federation.

Somewhere, sometime, there may have been a state that refrained from an evil act because its legal advisors could not say nuclear retribution would be illegal. It seems unlikely. But we know for sure that states such as India and Pakistan rely on the legal arguments of the nuclear states when they claim the right to become nuclear. So we must seize the chance the World Court has given us to rectify the legal confusion left over from the 1940s and '50s, and declare to and for all the planet, that the United States accepts the rule that no one may lawfully use a nuclear weapon. Then we must give the Russian Federation the assurances it needs so that all the nuclear powers may carry out the promise of Article VI and rid the world of their nuclear weapons. If we let the present window of relative opportunity pass, and if the Russian Federation is left with its thousands of warheads -- unstable, but cocked and ready to go -- we will deserve the curses of our descendants, if we have any.

Footnotes

1 Advisory Opinion in Response to the United Nations General Assembly Request Concerning the Legality of the Use of Nuclear Weapons in Armed Conflicts, I.C.J. Reports 1996, p. _____ (General List No. 95). The Court's straightened finances have delayed the official publication, so we will rely on International Legal Materials (Washington: American Society of International Law, 1996), Legality of the Threat or Use of Nuclear Weapons, 35 I.L.M. 809 (I.C.J., 1996). Slip opinions are available from various sources -- e.g., A.Malten@net.HCC.nl at The Hague.

An earlier petition from the World Health Organization was dismissed for want of standing in the petitioner. Legality of the Use by a State of Nuclear Weapons in Armed Conflict, I.C.J. Reports 1996, 66-224 (General List No. 93, July 8, 1996).

2 General Assembly Resolution 49/75 K, U.N. doc. A/49/PV.90 (1994), p. 91; 35 I.L.M. 809, 815. The resolution helped the Court out a bit by recalling "resolutions 1653 (XVI) of 24 November 1961, 33/71 B of 14 December 1978, 34/83 G of 11 December 1979, 35/152 D of 12 December 1980, 36/92 I of 9 December 1981, 45/59 of 4 December 1990 and 46/37 D of 6 December 1991, in which it [the General Assembly] declared that the use of nuclear weapons would be a violation of the Charter and a crime against humanity. . ." Nuclear Weapons, 35 I.L.M. 809, 815.

3 The Statute of the International Court of Justice, Article 65, paragraph 1. 59 Stat. 1055. Discussed in Nuclear Weapons, 35 I.L.M. 809, 817-819.

4 But see: Laurence de Chazournes and Philippe Sands, eds., International Law, the International Court of Justice, and Nuclear Weapons (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1999); John Burrows, Legality of Threat or Use of Nuclear Weapons: A Guide to the Historic Opinion of the International Court of Justice (Piscataway, N.J.: Transaction Publishers, 1998); Haralambos Athanasopulos, Nuclear Disarmament in International Law (Jefferson, N.C.: McFarland & Co., 2000); Ved P. Nanda and David Krieger, Nuclear Weapons and the World Court (Ardsley, N.Y.: Transnational Press, 1998).

5 United Nations Security Council statement of May 29, 1998; European Parliament statement of June 19, 1998.

6 The Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists regularly publishes nuclear scorecards. E.g., "U.S. Strategic Nuclear Forces, End of 1996," Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists, January/February 1997, 70-71.

7 Stansfield Turner, Caging the Nuclear Genie (Boulder: Westview Press, 1997). Paul Hendrickson, "Disarmed and Dangerous? Stansfield Turner Has an Explosive Idea to Reduce Nuclear Weapons," The Washington Post, October 7, 1997, C1.

8 George Lee Butler, "The General's Bombshell," Washington Post, January 12, 1997, C1; George Lee Butler, "Time to End the Age of Nukes," Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists, March/April 1997, 33-36. See also the proposals of Bruce Blair and former chair of the Senate Armed Services Committee, Senator Sam Nunn, The Washington Post, June 22, 1997, page C1; "An Evolving U.S. Nuclear Posture," by General Andrew Goodpastor, Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists, March/April 1996, page 52-55. Jonathan Schell, The Gift of Time (New York: Metropolitan, 1998) assembles a variety of views.

9 Several are quoted in the article cited above, The Washington Post, October 7, 1997, C1, C2, col. 5.

10 Nuclear Weapons, 35 I.L.M. 809, 831-832.

11 Nuclear Weapons, 35 I.L.M. 809, 813-831.

12 Nine of them are published in the International Legal Materials volume. Nuclear Weapons, 35 I.L.M. 809, 832-938. The others are available in slip opinions only.

13 Nuclear Weapons, Opinion of Weeramantry, 35 I.L.M. 809, 881, "Preliminary Observations on the Opinion of the Court," and 35 I.L.M. 809, 907-909, "The 1925 Geneva Gas Protocol" and Nuclear Weapons, Opinion of Koroma, 35 I.L.M. 809, 933, "Article 23(a) of the Hague Regulations". The third objecting judge cited the 1925 Geneva Gas Protocol in support of a general principle against weapons that cause unnecessary suffering. Nuclear Weapons, Opinion of Shahabuddeen, 35 I.L.M. 809, 870-871.

14 Nuclear Weapons, Opinion of Shahabuddeen, 35 I.L.M. 809, 862.

15 Nuclear Weapons, Opinion of Shahabuddeen, 35 I.L.M. 809, 862.

16 Which quotes the submissions of several nuclear states:

"Restrictions set by the rules applicable to armed conflicts in respect of means and methods of warfare definitely also extend to nuclear weapons" (Russian Federation, CR 95/29, p. 52);

"So far as the customary law of war is concerned, the United Kingdom has always accepted that the use of nuclear weapons is subject to the general principles of the jus in bello" (United Kingdom, CR 95/34, p. 45);

and

"The United States has long shared the view that the law of armed conflict governs the use of nuclear weapons just as it governs the use of conventional weapons" (United States of America, CR 95/34, p. 85)

Nuclear Weapons, 35 I.L.M. 809, 828.

The U.S. filing, "Written Statement of the Government of the United States of America," June 20, 1995 (unpublished), argued that nothing in international law prohibits the use of nuclear weapons per se.

17 Koroma, Nuclear Weapons, 35 I.L.M. 809, 926, and Shahabuddeen, 35 I.L.M. 809, 876, point out that this idea of an unlimited right to defend the state was rejected at Nuremberg.

18 Robert Musil, of Physicians for Social Responsibility, has suggested that even the great powers might have avoided possessing nuclear weapons if the world had first encountered them as Axis weapons used against San Francisco or London.

19 Koroma, Nuclear Weapons, 35 I.L.M. 809, 925-934; Oda, 35 I.L.M. 809, 843-861; Shahabuddeen ("My difficulty is with the second part" of (2)E.), 35 I.L.M. 809, 843; and Weeramantry ("the use or threat of use of nuclear weapons is illegal in any circumstances whatever"), 35 I.L.M. 809, 880.

20 Guillaume, Higgins, Koroma, Oda, Schwebel, Shahabuddeen, and Weeramantry. Nuclear Weapons, 35 I.L.M. 809, 831.

21 Nuclear Weapons, Opinion of Schwebel, 35 I.L.M. 809, 836, discussed below.

22 Nuclear Weapons, Opinion of Guillaume, slip opinion, not published in I.L.M.

23 Nuclear Weapons, Nuclear Weapons, Opinion of Higgins, 35 I.L.M. 809, 934-938.

24 Bedjaoui, Ferrari Bravo, Fleischhauer, Herczegh, Ranjeva, Shi, and Vereshchetin. Nuclear Weapons, 35 I.L.M. 809, 831.

25 But some of them probably would have. Fleischhauer said there was no ground to hold the law of humanity and the immunity of neutrals superior to the right of self-defense, Nuclear Weapons, 35 I.L.M. 809, 834-836, and Vereshchetin said an absolute prohibition would require a treaty. Nuclear Weapons, 35 I.L.M. 809, 833.

26 Literally the first: G.A. Res. 1(I), January 24, 1946.

27 Citing and quoting G.A. Res. 808 A (IX), November 4, 1954. See footnote 2, above, for other General Assembly resolutions.

28 And the Security Council resolution before the review conference, S. C. Res. 984 (1995), April 11, 1995.

29 S/23500, January 31, 1992.

30 Only India, Pakistan, and Israel have not signed the treaty and have bombs or the makings of bombs. Cuba and a handful of other small states have not signed: e.g., Cook Islands and Niue. Brazil, Chile, and Argentina have recently come on board. The dreaded "rogue states" -- Libya, Iraq, Iran, North Korea - have signed, as have all of the large nuclear powers: America, Britain, and Russia from the beginning, and China and France since 1992. The nations resulting from the breakup of the Soviet Union have all signed. They have all become non-nuclear except the Russian Federation. Not since the founding of the United Nations Organization has any proposal for international good behavior become so widely accepted.

31 "Universal International Law," 87 American Journal of International Law (1993) 529; Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties, Article 53. But see Anthony D'Amato, "It's a Bird, It's a Plane, It's Jus Cogens!" 6 Connecticut Journal of International Law (Fall 1990) 1 and Adam Steinfeld, "Nuclear Objections: The Persistent Objector and the Legality of the Use of Nuclear Weapons," 62 Brooklyn Law Review (Winter 1996) 1635-1686.

32 Nuclear Weapons, Opinion of Weeramantry, 35 I.L.M. 809, 879-924. Each page in the I.L.M. version reproduces two pages of the advance sheets.

33 Nuclear Weapons, Opinion of Shahabuddeen, 35 I.L.M. 809, 861-878.

34 Nuclear Weapons, Opinion of Koroma, 35 I.L.M. 809, 925-934.

35 Judgment of the International Military Tribunal at Nuremberg, 1946, Trial of German Major War Criminals before the International Military Tribunal (1947), vol. 1, 208, cited in Nuclear Weapons, Opinion of Koroma, 35 I.L.M. 809, 926.

36 I.C.J. Reports 1986, 96, cited in Nuclear Weapons, Opinion of Koroma, 35 I.L.M. 809, 926, 927.

37 Nuclear Weapons, Opinion of Koroma, 35 I.L.M. 809, 926, 933.

38 Shahabuddeen quoted a Red Cross reaction to Hiroshima and Nagasaki, 35 I.L.M. 809, 861, 864, and cited the Shimoda ruling condemning those urbicides, ibid., 869. Shimoda v. The State, Japanese Annual of International Law, vol. 8, 1964, p. 212, in Tokyo District Court. Weeramantry argued, 35 I.L.M. 809, 879, 895, that Hiroshima and Nagasaki did not show that modern nuclear war would be survivable, because, for one thing, they did not involve the modern risk of escalation. Other references to Hiroshima and Nagasaki were perfunctory or dealt with the destruction and injury done there. See Nuclear Weapons, Opinion of Koroma, 35 I.L.M. 809, 925, 928-929, for a summary of the statements of the mayors of Hiroshima and Nagasaki.

39 June 20, 1995, "Written Statement of the Government of the United States of America," Nuclear Weapons, General List no. 95, International Court of Justice, unpublished, cited above, note 16.

40 Nuclear Weapons, Opinion of Koroma, 35 I.L.M. 809, 925, 931.

41 Discussed above, note 13.

42 Nuclear Weapons, Opinion of Schwebel, 35 I.L.M. 809, 836, 837.

43 Nuclear Weapons, Opinion of Schwebel, 35 I.L.M. 809, 836, 838. Note that many nations have said explicitly, when supporting these limited bans, that they do not mean to validate bombs outside the ban. E.g., India's statement, United Nations Yearbook, 1959, 17-19.

44 Nuclear Weapons, Opinion of Schwebel, 35 I.L.M. 809, 836, 837-838.

45 Nuclear Weapons, Opinion of Schwebel, 35 I.L.M. 809, 836, 839.

46 Nuclear Weapons, Opinion of Schwebel, 35 I.L.M. 809, 836, 839.

47 Timothy Ferris, "Annals of Space: Is This the End?" The New Yorker, January 27, 1997, pages 44, 53-55, discusses Edward Teller's proposal to prepare for just such a contingency.

48 Likewise for nuclear terrorism, where nuclear weapons in the hands of national authorities would be of little value anyhow. Whatever the virtue or necessity of some residual nuclear capability remaining with some authority, we are so far from that level of disarmament that it is dishonest to talk about it. The present issue when we talk about law and rules is this: Can the general rule against nuclear weapons per se be destroyed by improbable thought-experiments, or does the general ban, with its authorization to keep nuclear weapons away from terrorists and rogue nations, stand as a general ban, whatever the limitations and defeasibility of all verbal rules?

49 June 20, 1995, filing of the United States, "Written Statement of the Government of the United States of America," unpublished, cited above, note 16.

50 Much skepticism has greeted Aziz's story. See "Nuclear Excuses," by William M. Arkin, Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists, May/June 1996, page 64.

51 Nuclear Weapons, Dispositif, (2)D., 35 I.L.M. 809, 831.

52 Nuclear Weapons, Dispositif, (2)D., 35 I.L.M. 809, 831. The Martens clause provides that, "populations and belligerents remain under the protection and empire of the principles of international law, as they result from the usages established between civilized nations, from the laws of humanity, and the requirements of the public conscience." Hague Convention II of 1899, "Convention with Respect to the Laws and Customs of War on Land," 32 Stat. 1803, 1805. See "Martens Clause," 3 Encyclopedia of Public International Law (New York: Elsevier, 1997) 326-327.

53 Nuclear Weapons, Dispositif, (2)D. 35 I.L.M. 809, 831; Opinion of the Court, 35 I.L.M. 809, paragraphs 22 and 78.

54 Nuclear Weapons, Opinion of the Court, 35 I.L.M. 809, paragraphs 41-44.

55 Nuclear Weapons, Dispositif, (2)E., 35 I.L.M. 809, 831.

56 Nuclear Weapons, Dispositif, (2)D., 35 I.L.M. 809, 831.

57 Nuclear Weapons, Opinion of the Court, 35 I.L.M. 809, paragraph 43.

58 Security Council Resolution of January 31, 1992, S/23500.

59 Bernard Baruch to John Foster Dulles, October 5, 1948: "The only thing that stands in the way of the over-running of Europe today is the atom bomb. When once we outlaw that, there is nothing to stop the Russian advance." Foreign Relations of the United States, 1948, vol. I, General: The United Nations, part 1, 448-450.